000 01794nam a22002657a 4500
003 ZW-GwMSU
005 20240301075405.0
008 240301b |||||||| |||| 00| 0 eng d
022 _a00222186
040 _aMSU
_bEnglish
_cMSU
_erda
050 _aHB73 JOU
100 1 _aLeeson, Peter T.
_eauthor
245 1 0 _aOrdeals
_cby Peter T. Leeson
264 _aChicago
_bUniversity of Chicago Press
_c2012
336 _2rdacontent
_atext
_btxt
337 _2rdamedia
_aunmediated
_bn
338 _2rdacarrier
_avolume
_bnc
440 _aJournal of law and economics
_vVolume 55, number 3
520 _aI argue that medieval judicial ordeals accurately assigned accused criminals’ guilt and innocence. They did this by leveraging a medieval superstition called iudicium Dei (judgments of God). According to that superstition, God condemned the guilty and exonerated the innocent through clergy-conducted physical tests. Medieval citizens’ belief in iudicium Dei created a separating equilibrium in which only innocent defendants were willing to undergo ordeals. Conditional on observing a defendant’s willingness to do so, the administering priest knew he or she was innocent and manipulated the ordeal to find this. My theory explains the peculiar puzzle of ordeals: trials of fire and water that should have condemned most persons who underwent them did the reverse. They exonerated these persons instead. Boiling water rarely boiled persons who plunged their arms in it. Burning iron rarely burned persons who carried it. Ordeal outcomes were miraculous, but they were miracles of mechanism design
650 _aChristianity
_xCriminals
650 _aEternal condemnation
_xGuilt
650 _aInnocence
_xLegal innocence
856 _uhttps://doi.org/10.1086/664010
942 _2lcc
_cJA
999 _c164022
_d164022